Home
About the Groundwork

Section I

The Good Will
The End of Practical Reason
Duty and Moral Worth
The Three Propositions
The Feeling of Respect
Conformity to Universal Law
Maxims of Action
The Lying Promise
The Inquiring Murderer

Section II

Hypothetical Imperatives
The Categorical Imperative
The Suicide Example
Perfect and Imperfect Duties
The Contradictions
Moral Realism
The Formula of Humanity
Deontology and Ethical Ends
The Formula of Autonomy
Autonomy and Heteronomy
The Kingdom of Ends

Section III

Freedom of the Will
Free in a Practical Respect
The Hidden Circle
Two Standpoints
The Deduction
Failure of the Deduction

 

The Hidden Circle “a kind of circle comes to light here from which, as it seems, there is no way to escape. We take ourselves as free in the order of efficient causes in order to think ourselves under moral laws in the order of ends; and we afterwards think ourselves as subject to these laws because we have ascribed to ourselves freedom of the will.”

Kant was concerned that the argument he was developing in Groundwork III might appear circular. Yet it can be hard at first to see how he might have introduced a circle with his argument there; and as a consequence, it is hard to see also how he avoided a circle, as he claims.

Exactly what is the circle? The circle is presented in a somewhat cumbersome way in the quotation above (Kant 1997, 55/4:450). A few pages later Kant redescribed it as follows:

we perhaps took as a ground the idea of freedom only for the sake of the moral law, so that we could afterwards infer the latter in turn from freedom. (57/4:453)

Stated in more contemporary language, the circle amounts to: (1) taking freedom as a necessary condition for subjection to morality; and then (2) taking morality as a necessary condition for freedom. The result of assuming both (1) and (2) is that freedom and morality turn out to be what Kant called “reciprocal concepts.” Each is necessary and sufficient for the other, which is fine. Only, it is circular to argue from one to the other without providing some independent proof of the one. We can argue for example from freedom to subjection to the moral law, but only provided we have some independent ground for assuming we are free. The circular reasoning Kant imagines would be arguing from our subjection to moral requirements to our freedom, and attempting to prove that we are subject to morality’s requirements on account of our being free.

Free in a practical respect. In Groundwork III Kant aims to show that there is a categorical imperative. By this he means that the moral law is objectively valid for our conduct, or that the restrictions expressed by the categorical imperative do, in fact, apply to us. In Section I of Groundwork III he shows why freedom is autonomy—meaning that the categorical imperative as expressed in the principle of autonomy can be derived from freedom. But then how can he show that we are free? If he will show that the principle of autonomy makes valid demands of us, he must show that we are free. In Section II of Groundwork III, his argument is that we are free in a practical respect provided we cannot act except under the idea of freedom. It now begins to look as if he may be reasoning in a circle. “Acting under the idea of freedom” seems to mean taking oneself to be responsible for what one does. That is something we do only once we see ourselves as deserving praise or blame, credit or demerit—and these presuppose a standard of judgment like the moral law. So it begins to look as if Kant’s basis for thinking we are free presupposes subjection to the moral law. It is plainly circular to argue that moral restrictions are objectively valid for us provided we are free, and that we are free provided we take ourselves to be morally responsible for what we do. Some non-moral reason must be given for thinking we are free, or for thinking we cannot act except under the idea of freedom. But that is not so easy to supply, especially to skeptical determinists who think that acting under the idea of freedom is an illusion.

A step into metaphysics. The way Kant attempts to remove the appearance of circular reasoning is by appealing to the transcendental distinction he had introduced in the Critique of Pure Reason: the distinction between appearances and things in themselves (see Kant 1998, A235-60/B294-315). He thinks that an independent case can be made for freedom, and therefore for the reality of the categorical imperative, by pointing out how, in addition to the natural world, we belong also, as rational beings, to an “intelligible world.” This is the confusing argument of the two standpoints.

 


References:

Kant, Immanuel (1997), Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

_____ (1998), Critique of Pure Reason, trans. and ed. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

Further Reading:

Allison, Henry E. (1990), Kant“s Theory of Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 218-21.

Paton, H. J. (1948), The Categorical Imperative, A Study of Kant’s Moral Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press), 255-6.

 

© Richard McCarty
Department of Philosophy & Religious Studies
East Carolina University
USA

Last modified: September 14, 2015

Terms of use.  Access to this copyrighted electronic document is open to everyone. Permission is hereby granted to quote any parts under 500 words, provided the author’s name is cited, along with the names and sources of any other authors quoted. Permission is also granted to quote any parts under 500 words in translation, provided the author’s name is cited, along with the names and sources of any other authors quoted. Duplicating this copyrighted material without obtaining prior, written permission is allowed only for local instructional use (“fair use”), which must include this statement of terms of use. Plagiarism is not allowed. Your professor can find this resource as easily as you did.